611 W. Union Street
Benson, AZ 85602
(520) 586-0800

Health Choice Integrated Care crisis Line
1-877-756-4090

NurseWise 24-Hour Crisis Line
1-866-495-6735

NAZCARE Warm Line
1-888-404-5530



SEABHS
611 W. Union Street
Benson, AZ 85602
(520) 586-0800

NurseWise 24-Hr Crisis Line
1-866-495-6735

NAZCARE Warm Line
1-888-404-5530


powered by centersite dot net

Getting Started
Here are some forms to get started. These can be printed and brought with you so that you can pre-fill out some known info ahead of time. More...


Health Sciences
Resources
Basic InformationLatest NewsQuestions and AnswersLinksBook Reviews
A Companion to GenethicsA Mind So RareA Mood ApartAcquiring GenomesAdaptive DynamicsAlterations of ConsciousnessAltered EgosAn Introduction to the Philosophy of MindAre We Hardwired?Being HumanBelief's Own EthicsBeyond GeneticsBiological Complexity and Integrative PluralismBody BazaarBrain Evolution and CognitionCloningCoherence in Thought and ActionConsciousness and the NovelConsciousness EmergingConsciousness EvolvingConsciousness in ActionConsciousness RecoveredConsciousness, Color, and ContentCreating Mental IllnessDarwinizing CultureDecoding DarknessDescriptions and PrescriptionsDynamics in ActionEmotionEmpathy and AgencyEvolutionEvolution and the Human MindEvolution's RainbowEvolutionary Origins of MoralityExploding the Gene MythFinding Consciousness in the BrainFrom Certainty to UncertaintyFurnishing the MindGenomeGetting HookedHeroes, Rogues, and LoversHeuristics and BiasesHow to Solve the Mind-Body ProblemHuman Nature and the Limits of ScienceHuman TrialsI of the VortexImproving Nature?In Our Own ImageIndividual Differences in Conscious ExperienceInformation ArtsIntelligence, Race, and GeneticsIntentions and IntentionalityMatters of the MindMind and MechanismModels of the SelfMy Double UnveiledNarrative and IdentityNaturalism and the Human ConditionNeurons and NetworksNorms of NatureOrigins of Human NatureOrigins of PsychopathologyOxford Guide to the MindPassionate EnginesPhilosophy and the NeurosciencesPhysicalism and Its DiscontentsPlaying God?PromiscuityProzac BacklashPsychiatry in the New MilleniumPsychological Concepts and Biological PsychiatryPsychological Dimensions of the SelfPsychologyRational Choice in an Uncertain WorldReclaiming CognitionRedesigning HumansSociological Perspectives on the New GeneticsSorting Things OutStrong FeelingsSurprise, Uncertainty, and Mental StructuresSynesthesia : A Union of the SensesThe Barmaid's BrainThe Birth of the MindThe Book of LifeThe Caldron of ConsciousnessThe Century of the GeneThe Cognitive Basis of ScienceThe Cognitive Neuroscience of ConsciousnessThe Conscious MindThe Debated MindThe Developing MindThe Dream DrugstoreThe Dynamic NeuronThe Empirical StanceThe Evolution of MindThe Illusion of Conscious WillThe Limits of Autobiography The Madness of Adam and EveThe Maladapted MindThe Mind's PastThe Misunderstood GeneThe Nature of ConsciousnessThe Nature of IntelligenceThe New PhrenologyThe Presence of MindThe Problem of the SoulThe Race for ConsciousnessThe Shattered SelfThe Significance of ConsciousnessThe Social Construction of What?The Terrible GiftThe Theory of OptionsThe Triumph of SociobiologyThe View from WithinThinks...Understanding CloningUnderstanding EmotionsUnderstanding the GenomeUp From DragonsWhat Genes Can't DoWhat It Means to Be 98 Percent ChimpanzeeWhere the Action IsWho Rules in ScienceWhy Smart People Can Be So StupidWhy We Lie
Related Topics

Medical Disorders
Mental Disorders
Mental Health Professions

by Sandra D. Mitchell
Cambridge University Press, 2003
Review by Arantza Etxeberria on May 21st 2004

Biological Complexity and Integrative Pluralism

This book shows that there are at least two ways in which the philosophy of biology contributes to the philosophy of science. One is the philosophical reflection on special questions posed in biology (those undertaken here all arise from an evolutionary perspective). The other is the discussion of general issues of the philosophy of science from the point of view of biology, so that its specific characteristics may define and configure the topics to be considered. This second line allows one to take into account problems arising beyond the scope of those found in physics, the "model science" of the classical approach. The book at hand presents developments in both of these lines, by considering the notion of complexity and defending pluralism on its behalf.

The main thesis of the book is that the complexity of biological systems shapes the form of the scientific explanations adequate for them and justifies pluralism ("Pluralism can simply reflect complexity" p. 3). This is a defense of pluralism that does not celebrate diversity just for the sake of it (in fact the author does her best to separate her position from other "anything-goes" appeals of pluralism), but argues from metaphysical (nature of complex systems and their processes) and epistemological (limitation of our explanations) grounds. In Part I various very specific aspects of this complexity are presented, whereas Part II explores the nature of scientific (more specifically biological) laws in the light of that complexity and finds a need for a different way (not normative but pragmatic) of characterizing them which leads to a plea for pluralism.

How do the essays in the book show or contribute to this thesis? In the first part three forms of complexity are distinguished: constitutive complexity, dynamic complexity and evolved diversity. Compositionally, complex living systems are constituted by non-randomly structured parts; examples are the multicellular organism, an ecosystem or an insect colony. Dynamically, they are the location for multiple, interacting causes. Evolutionarily, they display a variety of historically contingent, adaptive responses to environmental challenges. Nevertheless, Part I is not a purposefully written exposition of these three aspects of complexity, but a collection of (already and separately published) essays assembled under a new general overview based on the mentioned guidelines.

Constitutive complexity, emerging from how parts are arranged to form complex structures, is illustrated with an essay on a specific point (chapter 2): how does the organization of insect societies resemble that of a multicellular organism? The essay looks at the notion of superorganism, used by different authors throughout the XXth century and recently rescued to argue in favor pluralistic conceptions of the level at which selection acts. Although the author accords with the need for pluralism, she finds the superorganism metaphor misleading, because it is based on a parallel with a narrow definition of an organism (weismanian model) that obscures the fact that there exist very different forms of insect colony organization (as there are different forms of multicellular organizations), and because there are better forms to argue for a plurality of levels in terms of hierarchical complex systems.

Dynamic complexity is pictured through work on self-organizing models of Kaufmann´s NK type to explain different dynamical properties of insect organizations (chapter 3). The aim is to explore self-organizing properties of complex systems instead of adaptationist views in which all the constituents evolve atomistically through natural selection. The example of social insects is recurrent in several of the essays, some of them coauthored with Robert Page.

Chapter 4 is nominally devoted to evolved diversity, but is formed by some essays on central and debated topics on evolutionary biology such as the units of selection (this part contains a very useful analysis of how the solution to the problem requires to conceive evolution by natural selection as a two step process, and the consequences of reducing it to either a problem of replicators or of interactors), sociobiology (on whether behavioral traits can evolve by natural selection) and biological function (with a defense of an etiological notion in contrast with dispositional accounts). The three essays include insightful views of previous positions and well documented examples.

All in all, the three chapters of Part I present a certain bias towards evolutionary accounts of the nature of the biological and this has consequences on the notion of complexity considered by the author. More encompassing views are possible and necessary.

Part II of the book addresses the questions of biological laws and pluralism. In what respects the first problem the author first provides a good review of the issue of biological laws as discussed in the middle 90´s (chapter 5). According to the ECT (evolutionary contingency thesis), the laws that apply to living systems are either physical, chemical and mathematical or distinctively biological in that they describe a contingent outcome of evolution. Although the author accepts this contingency, its consequences must be tempered with a careful attention of the necessity shown by other kinds of laws that are not biological. The standard approach to the notion of scientific law admits that natural laws are contingent (their necessity is not logical), but they are understood according to a notion of necessity that mirrors logical necessity too closely. The author's analysis of the different conditions of the universe that account for the different levels of necessity that support different kinds of laws is very interesting. Her conclusion is that most studies of the notion of law in the philosophy of science have been developed under a "normative" conception related to the reductionist perspective favored by the ideal of the unity of science. In contrast, she defends a pragmatic approach to laws that provides a more adequate representational framework because the question of contingency may be related to that of how generalizations of various types function in different inferences to satisfy the pragmatic goals of science.

In the last chapter the author defends her version of pluralism, one whose challenge is to explain "how can a diverse, well confirmed, but irreducible set of theories be used collectively to achieve a more complete understanding than any of the theories taken in isolation?" (p. 115). The author considers the reasons for reductionism and defends an alternative based on the integration of compatible, not competitive, explanations.

Because the book is based on a collection of independently published articles, its appeal is in the local and detailed arguments and thoughts (which are fresh, well written and suggestive), whereas the global thread seems to be superimposed to them and sometimes underdeveloped. Readers interested in general philosophy of science and/or specific topics of the philosophy of biology will enjoy the book, including students, whereas those expecting an elaborate exposition of complexity may feel disappointed.

 

© 2004 Arantza Etxeberria

 

Arantza Etxeberria, Ph.D., Dept. of Logic and Philosophy of Science, University of the Basque Country, Spain