by David Cockburn St. Martin's Press, 2001 Review by Gregg Caruso on Jun 29th 2002 
Despite its
title, David Cockburns new book is less an introduction to contemporary issues
in the philosophy of mind, and more a book about personhood or
self-identity. The book revolves around
three approaches to the question What is a person? Cockburn focuses on the views of René Descartes, Ludwig
Wittgenstein, and current materialist or physicalist approaches to the
question. The main thesis of the book
is that both Descartes viewthat what I essentially am is a non-material
mind that is distinct from the body, as well as current
materialist/physicalist thinkingthat the correct description of a person is
that which is (or will be) offered by the physical sciencesare fundamentally
flawed. Cockburn instead defends a
Wittgensteinian alternative: The
alternative that has been presented in this book involves the idea that the
real methe thing that thinks, feels, and so onis the human being: one and the same as that which moves the
furniture, comforts my friends, and so on(143). According to Cockburn, fundamental place should be given to the
idea that the person is the human beingthe bodily being that we
encounter in our everyday interactions with othersand to the ways in which we
respond to each other in such interactions.
Although
the book deals with such traditional issues as the mind-body problem, mental
causation, and the other minds problem, its unclear who Cockburns intended
audience is. At times the book feels
more like an introduction to the philosophy of Descartes or Wittgenstein than
an introduction to the philosophy of mind.
Cockburn, for example, spends too much time examining the historical
views of Descartes and Wittgenstein for the book to act as a good survey to
current issues in mind. And such
chapters as The Cartesian Soul and the Paranormal, seem to serve little
purpose in such a short book. Cockburn,
however, is well aware of his misleading title. In fact, he writes: A
potential reader might reasonably expect that this book will be about the
mind. But the book is not about the
mind. It is about people: human beings(vii). Cockburns main claim is that philosophers,
and perhaps others, go wrong when they think that what needs to be investigated
is the nature of the mind. He argues
that there is a shared assumption between both the scientific approach to the
self, which he conflates with materialist or physicalist accounts that claim
that the mind is the brain, and dualist accounts. The assumption is that, the real person is something other than
the human being that we actually see when we meet another person(96).
The
problem, according to Cockburn, is that the mind-body division has become so
deeply entrenched and accepted by both parties. Both the physicalist and the dualist view the mind as that part
of the person in which thought, emotion, and sensation take place. The body is viewed as all the rest: the organic, but mechanical, part of the
person, which can be adequately characterized in the terms of natural
science. Cockburn argues that, The
mind-brain identity thesis simply takes over the mind/body distinction as it is
understood by Descartes(96). And
according to such a distinction, the bodywhat we see when we look at another
human beingis clearly not the entity that feels pains, gets angry, and so
on. He goes on to argue that the
dispute between materialists and dualists is simply a dispute about whether
the mindunderstood as the bit that does feel pain, get angry or think
about philosophyis just another material object or whether it is an entity of
a quite different, non-material, kind.
Its this shared assumption, Cockburn believes, that has set much of
contemporary philosophy off its rightful course: I am inclined to think that what the largest number of cleverest
philosophers have being saying about the mind over the last twenty or thirty
yearswhile it includes material of great importancebypasses many of the
issues that have been central to traditional philosophical thought about human
beings and their place in the world; and with that, bypasses a range of issues
that might be of concern to a reflective person who looks to philosophy for
some insight in this area(viii).
A good
subtitle to Cockburns book could be Souls, Science and Human Beings. The first two categories represent the two
approaches to the self that Cockburn rejects.
According to the first, what I essentially am is a non-material entitya
mind or soulwhich, while it in some sense inhabits this body for the
period of my life as a human being, is quite distinct from it. This, of course, is Descartes view. And I agree with Cockburn that it should be
rejected. Not only has it been largely
discredited by advances in the physical sciences, it has historically been
plagued by the insurmountable difficulty of explaining how the two supposed
substances of mind and body could interact at all. Its Cockburns treatment of the second
approach that I take issue with. For
one, his statement of the approach is vague and ill defined. In addition, it encompasses numerous
positions that really need to be separated out and examined independently. In the Preface, Cockburn defines the
approach as follows: The second of my
three approaches presents matters in this way, suggesting that it is to such
sciences that we must look if we are to attain a proper understanding of what a
person is: the description of a person,
and the explanations of her behavior, that are offered by physical science are
the fundamental truth about what she is.
While in one of its forms this approach suggests that the mind is the
brain and that mental states are states of the brain, that familiar thought
has, over the past thirty years, been modified in response to various
objections(vii). Although Cockburn
discusses some of these objections and modifications, it is here that I feel
the book disappoints. The philosophy of
mind literature is full of various divergent accounts for what it means to say
that the mind is the brain, and many of these accounts are conflated and given
the same treatment by Cockburn. Plus,
non-reductive physicalist accounts are hardly given any treatment at all. Any reader who turns to this book in hopes
of becoming familiar with the leading positions, arguments, objections, and
replies to the mind-body problem and related issues would be better suited
looking elsewhere. Two good suggestions
are Jaegwon Kims Philosophy of Mind (1996), and David Braddon-Mitchell
and Frank Jacksons Philosophy of Mind and Cognition (1996).
In defense
of Cockburn, his aim is not to give a survey of the literature but rather to
develop a third alternative. Cockburn
argues that the terms in which we normally understand the behavior of another
are not those of the natural sciences.
The language of smiles and angry glances has no place in physics as
it is normally understood(96). He
asks, then, in what sense can it be said that a proper description of what we
see when we see another human being can be given entirely in terms of the
language employed by the natural sciences?
As a third alternative, Cockburn suggests that it is the human being
herselfnot some part of her, or something that inhabits, and animates, her
bodythat thinks, gets angry, feels pains, and so on. It is the human being that we pity, love or fear. It is a central claim of the book that, to a
large extent, what the other two alternatives share is more important than what
they differ over. Cockburn argues that
these views share a distinctively sophisticated conception of the mind. They agree in the claim that the real
methe mind: the part that thinks, feels and so onis something distinct from
the bodily being that (brain surgeons aside!) others see or
touch(142-143). They differ, he
maintains, only in their views about the nature of this entity.
The
alternative that Cockburn defends, which arises from the views of Wittgenstein,
takes as primitive the human being and his/her behavior. At the most primitive level, Cockburn
argues, we do not see others as simply mechanical systems. Instead, we see the joy in anothers
face, we see the anger in the others eyes, we see people
laughing at jokes and writhing in agony, and so on. We do not see fleshi.e., a bodymoving in certain ways, and on
the basis of this infer that there is here a joyful person, or interpret
this as a person in pain. According to
Cockburn, we see the joy in her face.
We see the pain in her grimaces and hear it in her cries. And we see and hear these things, Cockburn
maintains, in the sense that we respond to her with, for example, a smile, or
with pity. The language in which we
describe what we see is an expression of these responses to others: responses that, Wittgenstein has suggested,
we should not regard as standing in need of any general
justification(102).
Although I find Cockburns
alternative approach interesting, its unclear what his main thesis ultimately
amounts to. He leaves largely undeveloped
his concept of a human being. Are we
to view this account as a form of behaviorism?
If not behaviorism, is it a form of non-reductive physicalism? If neither of these, does it commit itself
to a form of dualism? Although Cockburn
would reject such categories, its unclear how we are to understand such an
alternative. For example, its unclear
how we are to read comments like the following: Now that research makes it clear, no doubt, that there is some
kind of close connection between thought and what takes place in the brain;
but that does not, by itself, show that it is brains, rather than human beings,
that think(109-110). What exactly is
the human being here? Is it simply the
body and its behavior? Much more needs
to be said before one could make full sense of a statement like this.
I take it that Cockburns position
comes closest to a form of behaviorism.
This comes out most clearly in his discussion of Alan Turing and John
Searles views on whether machines can think.
He writes, if one holds that the person is the human being, and
that there is a linkof roughly the form suggested by Wittgensteinbetween the
idea of a creature as thinking and that creatures behaviour, then one
will maintain that the way in which Turing and Searle set up the issue of
artificial intelligence is misconceived(110). It is misconceived, he argues, because it offer us a seriously
improvised understanding of the input and output that it relevant to the
claim that some creature is thinking.
If Im correct in viewing
Cockburns positions as a form of behaviorism, then he has not really offered
us a true viable alternative; for he would first need to overcome all the well
know difficulties with such a position (a task, I believe, which is bound to fail!). But if Im mistaken, and Cockburn is
suggesting something different, then it remains a mystery how we are to
understand the proposal that the person is the human being. And its unclear how such a proposal would
help resolve any of the remaining difficulties that still confront the
philosophy of mind. In the end, I think
the book fails to have a clear audience.
Its not comprehensive enough, or diverse enough, in the positions it
covers to serve as a good introduction to someone unfamiliar with the central
issues in the philosophy of mind. And
its not powerful enough with regard to its positive proposal, due to its lack
of detail and development, to be of any real interest to professionals.
©
2002 Gregg Caruso
Gregg Caruso
is currently finishing up his PhD in Philosophy at The Graduate School and
University Center of the City University of New York.
|